Tuesday, June 20, 2017

Potential Jurors’ Moral Commitments and the Risk-Benefit Test in Products Liability Defect Cases

Originally published by Daniel Correa.

        In a product defect case involving serious bodily injury or death, the last thing a defense attorney wants to do is talk about how the benefit to society of the client’s product outweighs the risk of injury or death to a single person (or few persons). The risk-benefit test for product defects, however, requires a defense attorney to start that conversation and convince a jury that the benefits of a product outweigh its risks, even in the face of an actual injury or death that relates in some way to use of the product. This is a daunting task, especially if the defense attorney lacks information about jurors to determine whether they are really willing or able to engage in such a calculation.
        Trial attorneys are provided wide latitude during voir dire to investigate potential jurors’ prejudices and biases. Knowing how to press potential jurors’ moral reasoning will provide enough information to identify, above a mere guess, which jurors are most likely to engage in a risk-benefit calculation. An easy test exists to weed out potential jurors most inclined to reject a defendant-friendly risk-benefit analysis.

        There are generally two major moral views—please forgive this oversimplification: utilitarian and deontological. Utilitarians support the greatest good for the greatest number. Deontologists on the other hand, support treating each person as an end in herself and never as a means to an end. Utilitarians tend to be more receptive to risk-benefit analyses than deontologists.
The Trolley Car Problem
        A famous moral inquiry provides the perfect test to get potential jurors talking and to press their moral limits. Imagine you are overlooking a trolley track. In the distance you see a trolley car traveling at a high rate of speed and you notice that it lacks a driver. You also notice that it is headed straight toward five unaware people who will surely die if no one intervenes to stop or divert the trolley.
        You are the only person at the station. Next to you is a lever that will divert the trolley down the only other path. On that path, you notice a single unaware individual who will surely die if the trolley heads in that direction.
        What do you do? Do you pull the lever, thus diverting the trolley toward the one unaware individual? Or, do you allow the trolley to take its course toward the five unaware people? Remember, no matter what choice you make, death will ensue. The only question is, how many people will die? One or five?
        Same scenario, except there is no lever next to you that can divert the trolley. Instead, next to you stands a heavy person. The heavy person is turned away from you. The heavy person is exactly heavy enough to stop the trolley dead in its track. If you push the heavy person onto the track as the trolley approaches, his body will stop the trolley. The heavy person will die, but the five people on the track will live. If you do not push the heavy person onto the track to stop the trolley, the trolley will continue on its path and surely kill the five unaware people on the track.
        What do you do? Do you push the heavy person onto the track to save five people? Or, do you allow the trolley to take its course toward the five unaware people, who will surely die, and leave the heavy person alone?

        Most people opt into pulling the lever to divert the train, but opt into inaction when there is only the heavy person to stop the train. Moral philosophers debate the reasons for this seeming disjunction, because the results would be the same if you pulled the lever as if you pushed the heavy man on the track: one person dies, five people live. Some people explain the result in terms of agency: when you pull the lever, you are not complicit in the death of the one person on the track the same way that you would be complicit if you pushed a person to his death, even though you saved five people. But this complicit argument ignores the fact that an action is required in either scenario—pull a lever or push a person—and the person doing either action knows in advance the outcome—death.
Reason-Giving and Potential Juror Identification

        The upshot of asking potential jurors for their answers to this moral quandary is (1) you can identify potential jurors who will not even entertain pulling the lever. The value of life is something that outweighs any and all utilitarian calculations. You might try to rehabilitate this potential juror to see if she can never engage in any utilitarian calculation. For example, even truly committed deontologists waiver in their commitment when the stakes are substantially increased: If five hundred children were on one track and would surely die if you did not push the lever to divert the trolley onto the track with one person, would you pull the lever? Most likely, you will find, however, that truly committed deontologists are not good candidates for a products liability that potentially turns on the risk-benefit test. These are not the type of jurors we want in a product liability case.
        (2) You can identify potential jurors who will entertain pushing the heavy man. These are serious utilitarians. You at least know that these potential jurors are willing to engage in the type of calculation necessary to defend your client.

        (3) By engaging in this intellectual exercise, you treat the potential jury pool as your intellectual peers and may gain their trust. You will find that this exercise gets the jury pool talking and interested. They will laugh, show concern, and ask questions of their own.  

Curated by Texas Bar Today. Follow us on Twitter @texasbartoday.



from Texas Bar Today http://ift.tt/2rzeYj1
via Abogado Aly Website

No comments:

Post a Comment